home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
-
- We think it beyond dispute that a State has a strong and
- legitimate interest in the welfare of its young citizens, whose
- immaturity, inexperience, and lack of judgment may sometimes
- impair their ability to exercise their rights wisely. Hodgson v.
- Minnesota, 497 U. S., at 444 (opinion of Stevens, J.). A
- requirement of parental consent to abortion, like myriad other
- restrictions placed upon minors in other contexts, is reasonably
- designed to further this important and legitimate state interest.
- In our view, it is entirely rational and fair for the State to
- conclude that, in most instances, the family will strive to give
- a lonely or even terrified minor advice that is both
- compassionate and mature. Ohio v. Akron Center for Reproductive
- Health, 497 U. S., at 520 (opinion of Kennedy, J.); see also
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S., at 91
- (Stewart, J., concurring) (There can be little doubt that the
- State furthers a constitutionally permissible end by encouraging
- an unmarried pregnant minor to seek the help and advice of her
- parents in making the very important decision whether or not to
- bear a child). We thus conclude that Pennsylvania's parental
- consent requirement should be upheld.
-
-
- C
-
- Section 3209 of the Act contains the spousal notification
- rovision. It requires that, before a physician may perform an
- abortion on a married woman, the woman must sign a statement
- indicating that she has notified her husband of her planned
- abortion. A woman is not required to notify her husband if (1)
- her husband is not the father, (2) her husband, after diligent
- effort, cannot be located, (3) the pregnancy is the result of a
- spousal sexual assault that has been reported to the authorities,
- or (4) the woman has reason to believe that notifying her husband
- is likely to result in the infliction of bodily injury upon her
- by him or by another individual. In addition, a woman is
- exempted from the notification requirement in the case of a
- medical emergency. 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. 3209 (1990). See
- Appendix, ante, at 68-69.
-
- We first emphasize that Pennsylvania has not imposed a
- spousal consent requirement of the type the Court struck down in
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S., at
- 67-72. Missouri's spousal consent provision was invalidated in
- that case because of the Court's view that it unconstitutionally
- granted to the husband a veto power exercisable for any reason
- whatsoever or for no reason at all. Id., at 71. But this case
- involves a much less intrusive requirement of spousal
- notification, not consent. Such a law requiring only notice to
- the husband does not give any third party the legal right to make
- the [woman's] decision for her, or to prevent her from obtaining
- an abortion should she choose to have one performed. Hodgson v.
- Minnesota, supra, at 496 (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment in
- part and dissenting in part); see H. L. v. Matheson, 450 U.S., at
- 411, n. 17. Danforth thus does not control our analysis.
- Petitioners contend that it should, however; they argue that the
- real effect of such a notice requirement is to give the power to
- husbands to veto a woman's abortion choice. The District Court
- indeed found that the notification provision created a risk that
- some woman who would otherwise have an abortion will be prevented
- from having one. 947 F. 2d, at 712. For example, petitioners
- argue, many notified husbands will prevent abortions through
- physical force, psychological coercion, and other types of
- threats. But Pennsylvania has incorporated exceptions in the
- notice provision in an attempt to deal with these problems. For
- instance, a woman need not notify her husband if the pregnancy is
- result of a reported sexual assault, or if she has reason to
- believe that she wouldsuffer bodily injury as a result of the
- notification. 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. 3209(b) (1990). Furthermore,
- because this is a facial challenge to the Act, it is insufficient
- for petitioners to show that the notification provision might
- operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of
- circumstances. United States v. Salerno, 481 U. S. 739, 745
- (1987). Thus, it is not enough for petitioners to show that, in
- some worst-case circumstances, the notice provision will operate
- as a grant of veto power to husbands. Ohio v. Akron Center for
- Reproductive Health, 497 U. S., at 514. Because they are making
- a facial challenge to the provision, they must show that no set
- of circumstances exists under which the [provision] would be
- valid. Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). This they have
- failed to do.
-
- The question before us is therefore whether the spousal
- notification requirement rationally furthers any legitimate state
- interests. We conclude that it does. First, a husband's
- interests in procreation within marriage and in the potential
- life of his unborn child are certainly substantial ones. See
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S., at 69 (
- We are not unaware of the deep and proper concern and interest
- that a devoted and protective husband has in his wife's pregnancy
- and in the growth and development of the fetus she is carrying);
- id., at 93 (White, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
- part); Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S., at 541.
- The State itself has legitimate interests both in protecting
- these interests of the father and in protecting the potential
- life of the fetus, and the spousal notification requirement is
- reasonably related to advancing those state interests. By
- providing that a husband will usually know of his spouse's intent
- to have an abortion, the provision makes it more likely that the
- husband will participate in deciding the fate of his unborn
- child, a possibility that might otherwise have been denied him.
- This participation might in some cases result in a decision to
- proceed with the pregnancy. As Judge Alito observed in his
- dissent below, [t]he Pennsylvania legislature could have
- rationally believed that some married women are initially
- inclined to obtain an abortion without their husbands' knowledge
- because of perceived problems "such as economic constraints,
- future plans, or the husbands' previously expressed opposition"
- that may be obviated by discussion prior to the abortion.
- 947 F. 2d, at 726 (Alito, J., concurring in part and dissenting
- in part).
-
- The State also has a legitimate interest in promoting the
- integrity of the marital relationship. 18 Pa. Cons. Stat.
- 3209(a) (1990). This Court has previously recognized the
- importance of the marital relationship in our society. Planned
- Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, supra, at 69. In our
- view, the spousal notice requirement is a rational attempt by the
- State to improve truthful communication between spouses and
- encourage collaborative decisionmaking, and thereby fosters
- marital integrity. See Labine v. Vincent, 401 U. S. 532, 538
- (1971) ( [T]he power to make rules to establish, protect, and
- strengthen family life is committed to the state legislatures).
- Petitioners argue that the notification requirement does not
- further any such interest; they assert that the majority of wives
- already notify their husbands of their abortion decisions, and
- the remainder have excellent reasons for keeping their decisions
- a secret. In the first case, they argue, the law is unnecessary,
- and in the second case it will only serve to foster marital
- discord and threats of harm. Thus, petitioners see the law as a
- totally irrational means of furthering whatever legitimate
- interest the State might have. But, in our view, it is
- unrealistic to assume that every husband-wife relationship is
- either (1) so perfect that this type of truthful and important
- communication will take place as a matter of course, or (2) so
- imperfect that, upon notice, the husband will react selfishly,
- violently, or contrary to the best interests of his wife. See
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, supra, at 103-104
- (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (making
- a similar point in the context of a parental consent statute).
- The spousal notice provision will admittedly be unnecessary in
- some circumstances, and possibly harmful in others, but the
- existence of particular cases in which a feature of a statute
- performs no function (or is even counterproductive) ordinarily
- does not render the statute unconstitutional or even
- constitutionally suspect. Thornburgh v. American College of
- Obstetricians and Gynecologists, 476 U. S., at 800 (White, J.,
- dissenting). The Pennsylvania Legislature was in a position to
- weigh the likely benefits of the provision against its likely
- adverse effects, and presumably concluded, on balance, that the
- provision would be beneficial. Whether this was a wise decision
- or not, we cannot say that it was irrational. We therefore
- conclude that the spousal notice provision comports with the
- Constitution. See Harris v. McRae, 448 U. S., at 325-326 (It is
- not the mission of this Court or any other to decide whether the
- balance of competing interests . . . is wise social policy).
-
- D
-
- The Act also imposes various reporting requirements.
- Section 3214(a) requires that abortion facilities file a report
- on each abortion performed. The reports do not include the
- identity of the women on whom abortions are performed, but they
- do contain a variety of information about the abortions. For
- example, each report must include the identities of the
- performing and referring physicians, the gestational age of the
- fetus at the time of abortion, and the basis for any medical
- judgment that a medical emergency existed. See 18 Pa. Cons.
- Stat. 3214(a)(1), (5), (10) (1990). See Appendix, ante, at
- 69-71. The District Court found that these reports are kept
- completely confidential. 947 F. 2d, at 716. We further conclude
- that these reporting requirements rationally further the State's
- legitimate interests in advancing the state of medical knowledge
- concerning maternal health and prenatal life, in gathering
- statistical information with respect to patients, and in ensuring
- compliance with other provisions of the Act.
-
- Section 3207 of the Act requires each abortion facility
- to file a report with its name and address, as well as the names
- and addresses of any parent, subsidiary or affiliated
- organizations. 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. 3207(b) (1990). Section
- 3214(f) further requires each facility to file quarterly reports
- stating the total number of abortions performed, broken down by
- trimester. Both of these reports are available to the public
- only if the facility received state funds within the preceding 12
- months. See Appendix, ante, at 65-66, 71.
-
- Petitioners do not challenge the requirement that
- facilities provide this information. They contend, however, that
- the forced public disclosure of the information given by
- facilities receiving public funds serves no legitimate state
- interest. We disagree. Records relating to the expenditure of
- public funds are generally available to the public under
- Pennsylvania law. See Pa. Stat. Ann., Tit. 65, 66.1, 66.2
- (Purdon 1959 and Supp. 1991-1992). As the Court of Appeals
- observed, [w]hen a state provides money to a private commercial
- enterprise, there is a legitimate public interest in informing
- taxpayers who the funds are benefiting and what services the
- funds are supporting. 947 F. 2d, at 718. These reporting
- requirements rationally further this legitimate state interest.
-
- E
-
- Finally, petitioners challenge the medical emergency
- exception provided for by the Act. The existence of a medical
- emergency exempts compliance with the Act's informed consent,
- parental consent, and spousal notice requirements. See 18 Pa.
- Cons. Stat. 3205(a), 3206(a), 3209(c) (1990). The Act defines a
- medical emergency as [t]hat condition which, on the basis of the
- physician's good faith clinical judgment, so complicates the
- medical condition of a pregnant woman as to necessitate the
- immediate abortion of her pregnancy to avert her death or for
- which a delay will create serious risk of substantial and
- irreversible impairment of major bodily function. 3203.
- Petitioners argued before the District Court that the statutory
- definition was inadequate because it did not cover three serious
- conditions that pregnant women can suffer "preeclampsia,
- inevitable abortion, and prematurely ruptured membrane." The
- District Court agreed with petitioners that the medical emergency
- exception was inadequate, but the Court of Appeals reversed this
- holding. In construing the medical emergency provision, the
- Court of Appeals first observed that all three conditions do
- indeed present the risk of serious injury or death when an
- abortion is not performed, and noted that the medical
- profession's uniformly prescribed treatment for each of the three
- conditions is an immediate abortion. See 947 F. 2d, at 700-701.
- Finding that [t]he Pennsylvania legislature did not choose the
- wording of its medical emergency exception in a vacuum, the court
- read the exception as intended to assure that compliance with its
- abortion regulations would not in any way pose a significant
- threat to the life or health of a woman. Id., at 701. It thus
- concluded that the exception encompassed each of the three
- dangerous conditions pointed to by petitioners.
-
- We observe that Pennsylvania's present definition of
- medical emergency is almost an exact copy of that State's
- definition at the time of this Court's ruling in Thornburgh, one
- which the Court made reference to with apparent approval. 476
- U.S., at 771 ( It is clear that the Pennsylvania Legislature
- knows how to provide a medical- emergency exception when it
- chooses to do so). We find that the interpretation of the Court
- of Appeals in this case is eminently reasonable, and that the
- provision thus should be upheld. When a woman is faced with any
- condition that poses a significant threat to [her] life or
- health, she is exempted from the Act's consent and notice
- requirements and may proceed immediately with her abortion.
-
- IV
-
- For the reasons stated, we therefore would hold that each
- of the challenged provisions of the Pennsylvania statute is
- consistent with the Constitution. It bears emphasis that our
- conclu- sion in this regard does not carry with it any necessary
- approval of these regulations. Our task is, as always, to decide
- only whether the challenged provisions of a law comport with the
- United States Constitution. If, as we believe, these do, their
- wisdom as a matter of public policy is for the people of
- Pennsylvania to decide.
-
- Justice Scalia, with whom the Chief Justice, Justice White, and
- Justice Thomas join, concurring in the judgment in part and
- dissenting in part.
-
- My views on this matter are unchanged from those I set
- forth in my separate opinions in Webster v. Reproductive Health
- Services, 492 U. S. 490, 532 (1989) (Scalia, J., concurring in
- part and concurring in judgment), and Ohio v. Akron Center for
- Reproductive Health, 497 U. S. 502, 520 (1990) (Akron II)
- (Scalia, J., concurring). The States may, if they wish, permit
- abortion-on-demand, but the Constitution does not require them to
- do so. The permissibility of abortion, and the limitations upon
- it, are to be resolved like most important questions in our
- democracy: by citizens trying to persuade one another and then
- voting. As the Court acknowledges, where reasonable people
- disagree the government can adopt one position or the other.
- Ante, at 8. The Court is correct in adding the qualification
- that this assumes a state of affairs in which the choice does not
- intrude upon a protected liberty, ante, at 9 "but the crucial
- part of that qualification is the penultimate word. A State's
- choice between two positions on which reasonable people can
- disagree is constitutional even when (as is often the case) it
- intrudes upon a liberty in the absolute sense. Laws against
- bigamy, for example"which entire societies of reasonable people
- disagree with"intrude upon men and women's liberty to marry and
- live with one another. But bigamy happens not to be a liberty
- specially protected by the Constitution.
-
- That is, quite simply, the issue in this case: not
- whether the power of a woman to abort her unborn child is a
- liberty in the absolute sense; or even whether it is a liberty of
- great importance to many women. Of course it is both. The issue
- is whether it is a liberty protected by the Constitu- tion of the
- United States. I am sure it is not. I reach that conclusion not
- because of anything so exalted as my views concerning the concept
- of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of
- human life. Ibid. Rather, I reach it for the same reason I
- reach the conclusion that bigamy is not constitutionally
- protected"because of two simple facts: (1) the Constitution says
- absolutely nothing about it, and (2) the longstand- ing
- traditions of American society have permitted it to be legally
- proscribed. Akron II, supra, at 520 (Scalia, J., concurring).
-
- The Court destroys the proposition, evidently meant to
- represent my position, that liberty includes only those
- practices, defined at the most specific level, that were
- protected against government interference by other rules of law
- when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified, ante, at 5 (citing
- Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U. S. 110, 127, n. 6 (1989)
- (opinion of Scalia, J.). That is not, however, what Michael H.
- says; it merely observes that, in defining liberty, we may not
- disregard a specific, relevant tradition protecting, or denying
- protection to, the asserted right, 491 U. S., at 127, n. 6. But
- the Court does not wish to be fettered by any such limitations on
- its preferences. The Court's statement that it is tempting to
- acknowledge the authoritativeness of tradition in order to cur[b]
- the discretion of federal judges, ante, at 5, is of course
- rhetoric rather than reality; no government official is tempted
- to place restraints upon his own freedom of action, which is why
- Lord Acton did not say Power tends to purify. The Court's
- temptation is in the quite opposite and more natural direction
- "towards systematically eliminating checks upon its own power;
- and it succumbs."
-
- Beyond that brief summary of the essence of my position,
- I will not swell the United States Reports with repetition of
- what I have said before; and applying the rational basis test, I
- would uphold the Pennsylvania statute in its entirety. I must,
- however, respond to a few of the more outrageous arguments in
- today's opinion, which it is beyond human nature to leave
- unanswered. I shall discuss each of them under a quotation from
- the Court's opinion to which they pertain.
-
- The inescapable fact is that adjudication of substantive
- due process claims may call upon the Court in interpreting the
- Constitution to exercise that same capacity which by tradition
- courts always have exercised: reasoned judgment. Ante, at 7.
-
- Assuming that the question before us is to be resolved at
- such a level of philosophical abstraction, in such isolation from
- the traditions of American society, as by simply applying
- reasoned judgment, I do not see how that could possibly have
- produced the answer the Court arrived at in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.
- S. 113 (1973). Today's opinion describes the methodology of Roe,
- quite accurately, as weighing against the woman's interest the
- State's `important and legitimate interest in protecting the
- potentiality of human life.' Ante, at 28-29 (quoting Roe, supra,
- at 162). But reasoned judgment does not begin by begging the
- question, as Roe and subsequent cases unquestionably did by
- assuming that what the State is protecting is the mere
- potentiality of human life. See, e.g., Roe, supra, at 162;
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S. 52, 61
- (1976); Colautti v. Franklin, 439 U. S. 379, 386 (1979); Akron v.
- Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc., 462 U. S. 416, 428
- (1983) (Akron I); Planned Parenthood Assn. of Kansas City, Mo.,
- Inc. v. Ashcroft, 462 U. S. 476, 482 (1983). The whole argument
- of abortion opponents is that what the Court calls the fetus and
- what others call the unborn child is a human life. Thus,
- whatever answer Roe came up with after conducting its balancing
- is bound to be wrong, unless it is correct that the human fetus
- is in some critical sense merely potentially human. There is of
- course no way to determine that as a legal matter; it is in fact
- a value judgment. Some societies have considered newborn
- children not yet human, or the incompetent elderly no longer so.
-
- The authors of the joint opinion, of course, do not
- squarely contend that Roe v. Wade was a correct application of
- reasoned judgment; merely that it must be followed, because of
- stare decisis. Ante, at 11, 18-19, 29. But in their exhaustive
- discussion of all the factors that go into the determination of
- when stare decisis should be observed and when disregarded, they
- never mention how wrong was the decision on its face? Surely, if
- [t]he Court's power lies . . . in its legitimacy, a product of
- substance and perception, ante, at 23, the substance part of the
- equation demands that plain error be acknowledged and eliminated.
- Roe was plainly wrong "even on the Court's methodology of
- reasoned judgment, and even more so (of course) if the proper
- criteria of text and tradition are applied."
-
- The emptiness of the reasoned judgment that produced Roe
- is displayed in plain view by the fact that, after more than 19
- years of effort by some of the brightest (and most determined)
- legal minds in the country, after more than 10 cases upholding
- abortion rights in this Court, and after dozens upon dozens of
- amicus briefs submitted in this and other cases, the best the
- Court can do to explain how it is that the word liberty must be
- thought to include the right to destroy human fetuses is to
- rattle off a collection of adjectives that simply decorate a
- value judgment and conceal a political choice. The right to
- abort, we are told, inheres in liberty because it is among a
- person's most basic decisions, ante, at 7; it involves a most
- intimate and personal choic[e], ante, at 9; it is central to
- personal dignity and autonomy, ibid.; it originate[s] within the
- zone of conscience and belief, ibid.; it is too intimate and
- personal for state interference, ante, at 10; it reflects
- intimate views of a deep, personal character, ante, at 11; it
- involves intimate relationships, and notions of personal autonomy
- and bodily integrity, ante, at 15; and it concerns a particularly
- `important decisio[n],' ante, at 16 (citation omitted). But it
- is obvious to anyone applying reasoned judgment that the same
- adjectives can be applied to many forms of conduct that this
- Court (including one of the Justices in today's majority, see
- Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U. S. 186 (1986)) has held are not
- entitled to constitutional protection "because, like abortion,
- they are forms of conduct that have long been criminalized in
- American society. Those adjectives might be applied, for
- example, to homosexual sodomy, polygamy, adult incest, and
- suicide, all of which are equally intimate and deep[ly] personal
- decisions involving personal autonomy and bodily integrity, and
- all of which can constitutionally be proscribed because it is our
- unquestionable constitutional tradition that they are
- proscribable. It is not reasoned judgment that supports the
- Court's decision; only personal predilection. Justice Curtis's
- warning is as timely today as it was 135 years ago:
-
- [W]hen a strict interpretation of the Constitution,
- according to the fixed rules which govern the interpretation of
- laws, is abandoned, and the theoretical opinions of individuals
- are allowed to control its meaning, we have no longer a
- Constitution; we are under the government of individual men, who
- for the time being have power to declare what the Constitution
- is, according to their own views of what it ought to mean. Dred
- Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393, 621 (1857) (Curtis, J.,
- dissenting).
-
- Liberty finds no refuge in a jurisprudence of doubt.
- Ante, at 1.
-
- One might have feared to encounter this august and
- sonorous phrase in an opinion defending the real Roe v. Wade,
- rather than the revised version fabricated today by the authors
- of the joint opinion. The shortcomings of Roe did not include
- lack of clarity: Virtually all regulation of abortion before the
- third trimester was invalid. But to come across this phrase in
- the joint opinion "which calls upon federal district judges to
- apply an undue burden standard as doubtful in application as it
- is unprincipled in origin" is really more than one should have to
- bear.
-
- The joint opinion frankly concedes that the amorphous
- concept of undue burden has been inconsistently applied by the
- Members of this Court in the few brief years since that test was
- first explicitly propounded by Justice O'Connor in her dissent in
- Akron I, supra. See Ante, at 34. Because the three Justices now
- wish to set forth a standard of general application, the joint
- opinion announces that it is important to clarify what is meant
- by an undue burden, ibid. I certainly agree with that, but I do
- not agree that the joint opinion succeeds in the announced
- endeavor. To the contrary, its efforts at clarification make
- clear only that the standard is inherently manipulable and will
- prove hopelessly unworkable in practice.
-
- The joint opinion explains that a state regulation
- imposes an undue burden if it has the purpose or effect of
- placing a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an
- abortion of a nonviable fetus. Ibid.; see also ante, at 35-36.
- An obstacle is substantial, we are told, if it is calculated[,]
- [not] to inform the woman's free choice, [but to] hinder it.
- Ante, at 34. This latter statement cannot possibly mean what it
- says. Any regulation of abortion that is intended to advance
- what the joint opinion concedes is the State's substantial
- interest in protecting unborn life will be calculated [to] hinder
- a decision to have an abortion. It thus seems more accurate to
- say that the joint opinion would uphold abortion regulations only
- if they do not unduly hinder the woman's decision. That, of
- course, brings us right back to square one: Defining an undue
- burden as an undue hindrance (or a substantial obstacle) hardly
- clarifies the test. Consciously or not, the joint opinion's
- verbal shell game will conceal raw judicial policy choices
- concerning what is appropriate abortion legislation.
-
- The ultimately standardless nature of the undue burden
- inquiry is a reflection of the underlying fact that the concept
- has no principled or coherent legal basis. As The Chief Justice
- points out, Roe's strict-scrutiny standard at least had a
- recognized basis in constitutional law at the time Roe was
- decided, ante, at 22, while [t]he same cannot be said for the
- `undue burden' standard, which is created largely out of whole
- cloth by the authors of the joint opinion, ibid. The joint
- opinion is flatly wrong in asserting that our jurisprudence
- relating to all liberties save perhaps abortion has recognized
- the permissibility of laws that do not impose an undue burden.
- Ante, at 31. It argues that the abortion right is similar to
- other rights in that a law not designed to strike at the right
- itself, [but which] has the incidental effect of making it more
- difficult or more expensive to [exercise the right,] is not
- invalid. Ante, at 31-32. I agree, indeed I have forcefully
- urged, that a law of general applicability which places only an
- incidental burden on a fundamental right does not infringe that
- right, see R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. ___, ___ (1992) (slip
- op., at 11); Employment Division, Dept. of Human Resources of
- Ore. v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872, 878-882 (1990), but that principle
- does not establish the quite different (and quite dangerous)
- proposition that a law which directly regulates a fundamental
- right will not be found to violate the Constitution unless it
- imposes an undue burden. It is that, of course, which is at
- issue here: Pennsylvania has consciously and directly regulated
- conduct that our cases have held is constitutionally protected.
- The appropriate analogy, therefore, is that of a state law
- requiring purchasers of religious books to endure a 24-hour
- waiting period, or to pay a nominal additional tax of 1 cent.
- The joint opinion cannot possibly be correct in suggesting that
- we would uphold such legislation on the ground that it does not
- impose a substantial obstacle to the exercise of First Amendment
- rights. The undue burden standard is not at all the generally
- applicable principle the joint opinion pretends it to be; rather,
- it is a unique concept created specially for this case, to
- preserve some judicial foothold in this ill-gotten territory. In
- claiming otherwise, the three Justices show their willingness to
- place all constitutional rights at risk in an effort to preserve
- what they deem the central holding in Roe, ante, at 31.
-
- The rootless nature of the undue burden standard, a
- phrase plucked out of context from our earlier abortion
- decisions, see n. 3, supra, is further reflected in the fact that
- the joint opinion finds it necessary expressly to repudiate the
- more narrow formulations used in Justice O'Connor's earlier
- opinions. Ante, at 35. Those opinions stated that a statute
- imposes an undue burden if it imposes absolute obstacles or
- severe limitations on the abortion decision, Akron I, 462 U. S.,
- at 464 (O'Connor, J., dissenting) (emphasis added); see also
- Thornburgh v. American College of Obstetricians and
- Gynecologists, 476 U.S. 747, 828 (1986) (O'Connor, J.,
- dissenting). Those strong adjectives are conspicuously missing
- from the joint opinion, whose authors have for some unexplained
- reason now determined that a burden is undue if it merely imposes
- a substantial obstacle to abortion decisions. See, e.g., ante,
- at 53, 59. Justice O'Connor has also abandoned (again without
- explanation) the view she expressed in Planned Parenthood Assn.
- of Kansas City, Mo., Inc. v. Ashcroft, 462 U. S. 476 (1983)
- (dissenting opinion), that a medical regulation which imposes an
- undue burden could nevertheless be upheld if it reasonably
- relate[s] to the preservation and protection of maternal health,
- id., at 505 (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). In
- today's version, even health measures will be upheld only if they
- do not constitute an undue burden, ante, at 35 (emphasis added).
- Gone too is Justice O'Connor's statement that the State possesses
- compelling interests in the protection of potential human
- life . . . throughout pregnancy, Akron I, supra, at 461 (emphasis
- added); see also Ashcroft, supra, at 505 (O'Connor, J.,
- concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part);
- Thornburgh, supra, at 828 (O'Connor, J., dissenting); instead,
- the State's interest in unborn human life is stealthily
- downgraded to a merely substantial or profound interest,
- ante, at 34, 36. (That had to be done, of course, since
- designating the interest as compelling throughout pregnancy would
- have been, shall we say, a substantial obstacle to the joint
- opinion's determined effort to reaffirm what it views as the
- central holding of Roe. See Akron I, 462 U.S., at 420, n. 1.)
- And viability is no longer the arbitrary dividing line previously
- decried by Justice O'Connor in Akron I, id., at 461; the Court
- now announces that the attainment of viability may continue to
- serve as the critical fact, ante, at 18. It is difficult to
- maintain the illusion that we are interpreting a Constitution
- rather than inventing one, when we amend its provisions so
- breezily.
-
- Because the portion of the joint opinion adopting and
- describing the undue-burden test provides no more useful guidance
- than the empty phrases discussed above, one must turn to the 23
- pages applying that standard to the present facts for further
- guidance. In evaluating Pennsylvania's abortion law, the joint
- opinion relies extensively on the factual findings of the
- District Court, and repeatedly qualifies its conclusions by
- noting that they are contingent upon the record developed in this
- case. Thus, the joint opinion would uphold the 24-hour waiting
- period contained in the Pennsylvania statute's informed consent
- provi- sion, 18 Pa. Cons. Stat. 3205 (1990), because the record
- evidence shows that in the vast majority of cases, a 24-hour
- delay does not create any appreciable health risk, ante, at 43.
- The three Justices therefore conclude that on the record before
- us, . . . we are not convinced that the 24-hour waiting period
- constitutes an undue burden. Ante, at 44-45. The requirement
- that a doctor provide the information pertinent to informed
- consent would also be upheld because there is no evidence on this
- record that [this requirement] would amount in practical terms to
- a substantial obstacle to a woman seeking an abortion, ante, at
- 42. Similarly, the joint opinion would uphold the reporting
- requirements of the Act, 3207, 3214, because there is no . . .
- showing on the record before us that these requirements
- constitute a substantial obstacle to abortion decisions. Ante,
- at 59. But at the same time the opinion pointedly observes that
- these reporting requirements may increase the costs of abortions
- and that at some point [that fact] could become a substantial
- obstacle, ibid. Most significantly, the joint opinion's
- conclusion that the spousal notice requirement of the Act, see
- 3209, imposes an undue burden is based in large measure on the
- District Court's detailed findings of fact, which the joint
- opinion sets out at great length. Ante, at 45-49.
-
- I do not, of course, have any objection to the notion
- that, in applying legal principles, one should rely only upon the
- facts that are contained in the record or that are properly
- subject to judicial notice. But what is remarkable about the
- joint opinion's fact-intensive analysis is that it does not
- result in any measurable clarification of the undue burden
- standard. Rather, the approach of the joint opinion is, for the
- most part, simply to highlight certain facts in the record that
- apparently strike the three Justices as particularly significant
- in establishing (or refuting) the existence of an undue burden;
- after describing these facts, the opinion then simply announces
- that the provision either does or does not impose a substantial
- obstacle or an undue burden. See, e.g., ante, at 38, 42, 44-45,
- 45, 52, 53, 59. We do not know whether the same conclusions
- could have been reached on a different record, or in what
- respects the record would have had to differ before an opposite
- conclusion would have been appropriate. The inherently
- standardless nature of this inquiry invites the district judge to
- give effect to his personal preferences about abortion. By
- finding and relying upon the right facts, he can invalidate, it
- would seem, almost any abortion restriction that strikes him as
- undue"subject, of course, to the possibility of being reversed by
- a Circuit Court or Supreme Court that is as unconstrained in
- reviewing his decision as he was in making it.
-
- To the extent I can discern any meaningful content in the
- undue burden standard as applied in the joint opinion, it appears
- to be that a State may not regulate abortion in such a way as to
- reduce significantly its incidence. The joint opinion repeatedly
- emphasizes that an important factor in the undue burden analysis
- is whether the regulation prevent[s] a significant number of
- women from obtaining an abortion, ante, at 52; whether a
- significant number of women . . . are likely to be deterred from
- procuring an abortion, ibid.; and whether the regulation often
- deters women from seeking abortions, ante, at 55-56. We are not
- told, however, what forms of deterrence are impermissible or what
- degree of success in deterrence is too much to be tolerated. If,
- for example, a State required a woman to read a pamphlet
- describing, with illustrations, the facts of fetal development
- before she could obtain an abortion, the effect of such
- legislation might be to deter a significant number of women from
- procuring abortions, thereby seemingly allowing a district judge
- to invalidate it as an undue burden. Thus, despite flowery
- rhetoric about the State's substantial and profound interest in
- potential human life, and criticism of Roe for under-valuing that
- interest, the joint opinion permits the State to pursue that
- interest only so long as it is not too successful. As Justice
- Blackmun recognizes (with evident hope), ante, at 5, the undue
- burden standard may ultimately require the invalidation of each
- provision upheld today if it can be shown, on a better record,
- that the State is too effectively express[ing] a preference for
- childbirth over abortion, ante, at 41. Reason finds no refuge in
- this jurisprudence of confusion.
-
- While we appreciate the weight of the arguments . . .
- that Roe should be overruled, the reservations any of us may have
- in reaffirming the central holding of Roe are outweighed by the
- explication of individual liberty we have given combined with the
- force of stare decisis. Ante, at 11.
-
- The Court's reliance upon stare decisis can best be
- described as contrived. It insists upon the necessity of
- adhering not to all of Roe, but only to what it calls the central
- holding. It seems to me that stare decisis ought to be applied
- even to the doctrine of stare decisis, and I confess never to
- have heard of this new,
- keep-what-you-want-and-throw-away-the-rest version. I wonder
- whether, as applied to Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137 (1803),
- for example, the new version of stare decisis would be satisfied
- if we allowed courts to review the constitutionality of only
- those statutes that (like the one in Marbury) pertain to the
- jurisdiction of the courts.
-
- I am certainly not in a good position to dispute that the
- Court has saved the central holding of Roe, since to do that
- effectively I would have to know what the Court has saved, which
- in turn would require me to understand (as I do not) what the
- undue burden test means. I must confess, however, that I have
- always thought, and I think a lot of other people have always
- thought, that the arbitrary trimester framework, which the Court
- today discards, was quite as central to Roe as the arbitrary
- viability test, which the Court today retains. It seems
- particularly ungrateful to carve the trimester framework out of
- the core of Roe, since its very rigidity (in sharp contrast to
- the utter indeterminability of the undue burden test) is probably
- the only reason the Court is able to say, in urging stare
- decisis, that Roe has in no sense proven `unworkable,' ante, at
- 13. I suppose the Court is entitled to call a central holding
- whatever it wants to call a central holding "which is, come to
- think of it, perhaps one of the difficulties with this modified
- version of stare decisis. I thought I might note, however, that
- the following portions of Roe have not been saved:
-
- *Under Roe, requiring that a woman seeking an abortion be
- provided truthful information about abortion before giving
- informed written consent is unconstitutional, if the information
- is designed to influence her choice, Thornburgh, 476 U. S., at
- 759-765; Akron I, 462 U. S., at 442-445. Under the joint
- opinion's undue burden regime (as applied today, at least) such a
- requirement is constitu- tional, ante, at 38-42.
-
- *Under Roe, requiring that information be provided by a doctor,
- rather than by nonphysician counselors, is unconstitutional,
- Akron I, supra, at 446-449. Under the undue burden regime (as
- applied today, at least) it is not, ante, at 42.
-
- *Under Roe, requiring a 24-hour waiting period between the time
- the woman gives her informed consent and the time of the abortion
- is unconstitutional, Akron I, supra, at 449-451. Under the undue
- burden regime (as applied today, at least) it is not, ante, at
- 43-45.
-
- *Under Roe, requiring detailed reports that include demographic
- data about each woman who seeks an abortion and various
- information about each abortion is unconstitutional, Thornburgh,
- supra, at 765-768. Under the undue burden regime (as applied
- today, at least) it generally is not, ante, at 58-59.
-
- Where, in the performance of its judicial duties, the
- Court decides a case in such a way as to resolve the sort of
- intensely divisive controversy reflected in Roe . . . , its
- decision has a dimension that the resolution of the normal case
- does not carry. It is the dimension present whenever the Court's
- interpretation of the Constitution calls the contending sides of
- a national controversy to end their national division by
- accepting a common mandate rooted in the Constitution.
- Ante, at 24.
-
- The Court's description of the place of Roe in the social
- history of the United States is unrecognizable. Not only did Roe
- not, as the Court suggests, resolve the deeply divisive issue of
- abortion; it did more than anything else to nourish it, by
- elevating it to the national level where it is infinitely more
- difficult to resolve. National politics were not plagued by
- abortion protests, national abortion lobbying, or abortion
- marches on Congress, before Roe v. Wade was decided. Profound
- disagreement existed among our citizens over the issue "as it
- does over other issues, such as the death penalty" but that
- disagreement was being worked out at the state level. As with
- many other issues, the division of sentiment within each State
- was not as closely balanced as it was among the population of the
- Nation as a whole, meaning not only that more people would be
- satis- fied with the results of state-by-state resolution, but
- also that those results would be more stable. Pre-Roe, moreover,
- political compromise was possible.
-
- Roe's mandate for abortion-on-demand destroyed the
- compromises of the past, rendered compromise impossible for the
- future, and required the entire issue to be resolved uniformly,
- at the national level. At the same time, Roe created a vast new
- class of abortion consumers and abortion proponents by
- eliminating the moral opprobrium that had attached to the act.
- (If the Constitution guarantees abor-tion, how can it be bad?"
- not an accurate line of thought, but a natural one.) Many favor
- all of those developments, and it is not for me to say that they
- are wrong. But to portray Roe as the statesmanlike settlement of
- a divisive issue, a jurisprudential Peace of Westphalia that is
- worth preserving, is nothing less than Orwellian. Roe fanned
- into life an issue that has inflamed our national politics in
- general, and has obscured with its smoke the selection of
- Justices to this Court in particular, ever since. And by keeping
- us in the abortion-umpiring business, it is the perpetuation of
- that disruption, rather than of any pax Roeana, that the Court's
- new majority decrees.
-
- [T]o overrule under fire . . . would subvert the Court's
- legitimacy . . . .
-
- To all those who will be . . . tested by following, the
- Court implicitly undertakes to remain stead- fast . . . . The
- promise of constancy, once given, binds its maker for as long as
- the power to stand by the decision survives and . . . the
- commitment [is not] obsolete. . . .
-
- [The American people's] belief in themselves as . . . a
- people [who aspire to live according to the rule of law] is not
- readily separable from their understanding of the Court invested
- with the authority to decide their constitutional cases and speak
- before all others for their constitutional ideals. If the
- Court's legitimacy should be undermined, then, so would the
- country be in its very ability to see itself through its
- constitutional ideals.
-
- Ante, at 25-26.
-
- The Imperial Judiciary lives. It is instructive to
- compare this Nietzschean vision of us unelected, life-tenured
- judges" leading a Volk who will be tested by following, and whose
- very belief in themselves is mystically bound up in their
- understanding of a Court that speak[s] before all others for
- their constitutional ideals" with the somewhat more modest role
- envisioned for these lawyers by the Founders.
-
- The judiciary . . . has . . . no direction either of the
- strength or of the wealth of the society, and can take no active
- resolution whatever. It may truly be said to have neither Force
- nor Will but merely judgment . . . . The Federalist No. 78, pp.
- 393-394 (G. Wills ed. 1982). Or, again, to compare this ecstasy
- of a Supreme Court in which there is, especially on controversial
- matters, no shadow of change or hint of alteration ( There is a
- limit to the amount of error that can plausibly be imputed to
- prior courts, ante, at 24), with the more democratic views of a
- more humble man:
-
- [T]he candid citizen must confess that if the policy of
- the Government upon vital questions affecting the whole people is
- to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of the Supreme Court, . . .
- the people will have ceased to be their own rulers, having to
- that extent practically resigned their Government into the hands
- of that eminent tribunal. A. Lincoln, First Inaugural Address
- (Mar. 4, 1861), reprinted in Inaugural Addresses of the
- Presidents of the United States, S. Doc. No. 101-10, p. 139
- (1989). It is particularly difficult, in the circumstances of
- the present decision, to sit still for the Court's lengthy
- lecture upon the virtues of constancy, ante, at 26, of
- remain[ing] steadfast, id., at 25, of adhering to principle, id.,
- passim. Among the five Justices who purportedly adhere to Roe,
- at most three agree upon the principle that constitutes adherence
- (the joint opinion's undue burden standard)"and that
- principle is inconsistent with Roe, see 410 U. S., at 154-156.
- To make matters worse, two of the three, in order thus to remain
- steadfast, had to abandon previously stated positions. See n. 4
- supra; see supra, at 11-12. It is beyond me how the Court
- expects these accommodations to be accepted as grounded truly in
- principle, not as compromises with social and political pressures
- having, as such, no bearing on the principled choices that the
- Court is obliged to make. Ante, at 23. The only principle the
- Court adheres to, it seems to me, is the principle that the Court
- must be seen as standing by Roe. That is not a principle of law
- (which is what I thought the Court was talking about), but a
- principle of Realpolitik" and a wrong one at that.
-
- I cannot agree with, indeed I am appalled by, the Court's
- suggestion that the decision whether to stand by an erroneous
- constitutional decision must be strongly influenced"against
- overruling, no less"by the substantial and continuing public
- opposition the decision has generated. The Court's judgment that
- any other course would subvert the Court's legitimacy must be
- another consequence of reading the error-filled history book that
- described the deeply divided country brought together by Roe. In
- my history-book, the Court was covered with dishonor and deprived
- of legitimacy by Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393 (1857), an
- erroneous (and widely opposed) opinion that it did not abandon,
- rather than by West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 300 U. S. 379
- (1937), which produced the famous switch in time from the Court's
- erroneous (and widely opposed) constitutional opposition to the
- social measures of the New Deal. (Both Dred Scott and one line
- of the cases resisting the New Deal rested upon the concept of
- substantive due process that the Court praises and employs today.
- Indeed, Dred Scott was very possibly the first application of
- substantive due process in the Supreme Court, the original
- precedent for Lochner v. New York and Roe v. Wade. D. Currie,
- The Constitution in the Supreme Court 271 (1985) (footnotes
- omitted).)
-
- But whether it would subvert the Court's legitimacy or
- not, the notion that we would decide a case differently from the
- way we otherwise would have in order to show that we can stand
- firm against public disapproval is frightening. It is a bad
- enough idea, even in the head of someone like me, who believes
- that the text of the Constitution, and our traditions, say what
- they say and there is no fiddling with them. But when it is in
- the mind of a Court that believes the Constitution has an
- evolving meaning, see ante, at 6; that the Ninth Amendment's
- reference to othe[r] rights is not a disclaimer, but a charter
- for action, ibid.; and that the function of this Court is to
- speak before all others for [the people's] constitutional ideals
- unrestrained by meaningful text or tradition"then the notion that
- the Court must adhere to a decision for as long as the decision
- faces great opposition and the Court is under fire acquires a
- character of almost czarist arrogance. We are offended by these
- marchers who descend upon us, every year on the anniversary of
- Roe, to protest our saying that the Constitution requires what
- our society has never thought the Constitution requires. These
- people who refuse to be tested by following must be taught a
- lesson. We have no Cossacks, but at least we can stubbornly
- refuse to abandon an erroneous opinion that we might otherwise
- change"to show how little they intimidate us.
-
- Of course, as the Chief Justice points out, we have been
- subjected to what the Court calls political pressure by both
- sides of this issue. Ante, at 21. Maybe today's decision not to
- over- rule Roe will be seen as buckling to pressure from that
- direction. Instead of engaging in the hopeless task of
- predicting public perception "a job not for lawyers but for
- political campaign managers" the Justices should do what is
- legally right by asking two questions: (1) Was Roe correctly
- decided? (2) Has Roe succeeded in producing a settled body of
- law? If the answer to both questions is no, Roe should
- undoubtedly be overruled.
-
- In truth, I am as distressed as the Court is "and
- expressed my distress several years ago, see Webster, 492 U. S.,
- at 535" about the political pressure directed to the Court: the
- marches, the mail, the protests aimed at inducing us to change
- our opinions. How upsetting it is, that so many of our citizens
- (good people, not lawless ones, on both sides of this abortion
- issue, and on various sides of other issues as well) think that
- we Justices should properly take into account their views, as
- though we were engaged not in ascertaining an objective law but
- in determining some kind of social consensus. The Court would
- profit, I think, from giving less attention to the fact of this
- distressing phenomenon, and more attention to the cause of it.
- That cause permeates today's opinion: a new mode of
- constitutional adjudication that relies not upon text and
- traditional practice to determine the law, but upon what the
- Court calls reasoned judgment, ante, at 7, which turns out to be
- nothing but philosophical predilection and moral intuition. All
- manner of liberties, the Court tells us, inhere in the
- Constitution and are enforceable by this Court "not just those
- mentioned in the text or established in the traditions of our
- society." Ante, at 5-6. Why even the Ninth Amendment "which
- says only that [t]he enumeration in the Constitution of certain
- rights shall not be construed to deny or disparage others
- retained by the people" is, despite our contrary understanding
- for almost 200 years, a literally boundless source of additional,
- unnamed, unhinted-at rights, definable and enforceable by us,
- through reasoned judgment. Ante, at 6-7.
-
- What makes all this relevant to the bothersome
- application of political pressure against the Court are the twin
- facts that the American people love democracy and the American
- people are not fools. As long as this Court thought (and the
- people thought) that we Justices were doing essentially lawyers'
- work up here"reading text and discerning our society's
- traditional understanding of that text"the public pretty much
- left us alone. Texts and traditions are facts to study, not
- convictions to demonstrate about. But if in reality our process
- of constitutional adjudication consists primarily of making value
- judgments; if we can ignore a long and clear tradition clarifying
- an ambiguous text, as we did, for example, five days ago in
- declaring unconstitutional invocations and benedictions at
- public- high-school graduation ceremonies, Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.
- S. ___ (1992); if, as I say, our pronouncement of constitutional
- law rests primarily on value judgments, then a free and
- intelligent people's attitude towards us can be expected to be
- (ought to be) quite different. The people know that their value
- judgments are quite as good as those taught in any law school
- "maybe better." If, indeed, the liberties protected by the
- Constitution are, as the Court says, undefined and unbounded,
- then the people should demonstrate, to protest that we do not
- implement their values instead of ours. Not only that, but
- confirmation hearings for new Justices should deteriorate into
- question-and-answer sessions in which Senators go through a list
- of their constituents' most favored and most disfavored alleged
- constitu- tional rights, and seek the nominee's commitment to
- support or oppose them. Value judgments, after all, should be
- voted on, not dictated; and if our Constitution has somehow
- accidently committed them to the Supreme Court, at least we can
- have a sort of plebiscite each time a new nominee to that body is
- put forward. Justice Blackmun not only regards this prospect
- with equanimity, he solicits it, ante, at 22-23.
-
- * * *
-
- There is a poignant aspect to today's opinion. Its
- length, and what might be called its epic tone, suggest that its
- authors believe they are bringing to an end a troublesome era in
- the history of our Nation and of our Court. It is the dimension
- of authority, they say, to cal[l] the contending sides of
- national controversy to end their national division by accepting
- a common mandate rooted in the Constitution. Ante, at 24.
-
- There comes vividly to mind a portrait by Emanuel Leutze
- that hangs in the Harvard Law School: Roger Brooke Taney,
- painted in 1859, the 82d year of his life, the 24th of his Chief
- Justiceship, the second after his opinion in Dred Scott. He is
- all in black, sitting in a shadowed red armchair, left hand
- resting upon a pad of paper in his lap, right hand hanging
- limply, almost lifelessly, beside the inner arm of the chair. He
- sits facing the viewer, and staring straight out. There seems to
- be on his face, and in his deep-set eyes, an expression of
- profound sadness and disillusionment. Perhaps he always looked
- that way, even when dwelling upon the happiest of thoughts. But
- those of us who know how the lustre of his great Chief
- Justiceship came to be eclipsed by Dred Scott cannot help
- believing that he had that case "its already apparent
- consequences for the Court, and its soon-to-be-played-out
- consequences for the Nation" burning on his mind. I expect that
- two years earlier he, too, had thought himself call[ing] the
- contending sides of national controversy to end their national
- division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the
- Constitution.
-
- It is no more realistic for us in this case, than it was
- for him in that, to think that an issue of the sort they both
- involved "an issue involving life and death, freedom and
- subjugation" can be speedily and finally settled by the Supreme
- Court, as President James Buchanan in his inaugural address said
- the issue of slavery in the territories would be. See Inaugural
- Addresses of the Presidents of the United States, S. Doc. No.
- 101-10, p. 126 (1989). Quite to the contrary, by foreclosing all
- democratic outlet for the deep passions this issue arouses, by
- banishing the issue from the political forum that gives all
- participants, even the losers, the satisfaction of a fair hearing
- and an honest fight, by continuing the imposition of a rigid
- national rule instead of allowing for regional differences, the
- Court merely prolongs and intensifies the anguish.
-
- We should get out of this area, where we have no right to
- be, and where we do neither ourselves nor the country any good
- by remaining.
-